Is the CIA in the Drone Kill Chain? (Answer: Likely.)

Is the CIA in the Drone Kill Chain? (Answer: Likely.)

Wells Bennett calls my attention to this statement by Marc Ambinder in a recent article in The Week entitled “Five Truths About the Drone War”:

The CIA does not “fly” drones. It “owns” drones, but the Air Force flies them. The Air Force coordinates (and deconflicts) their use through the CIA’s Office of Military Affairs, which is run by an Air Force general. The Air Force performs maintenance on them. The Air Force presses the button that releases the missile. There are no CIA civilians piloting remote controlled air vehicles. The Agency has about 40 unmanned aerial vehicles in its worldwide arsenal, about 30 of which are deployed in the Middle East and Africa. Most of these thingies are equipped with sophisticated surveillance gear. A few of them are modified to launch missiles. The Air Force owns many more “lethal” RPVs, but it uses them in the contiguous battlefield of Afghanistan.

Wells points out at Lawfare that “if Ambinder is correct, then it is military personnel who do the drone-flying and the button-pushing, and military personnel can invoke a public authority justification for strikes implicating 1119, in Kevin’s view.” In other words, Wells suggests that it might be irrelevant whether CIA officers are entitled to a public authority defence, because they may not actually be involved in lethal drone attacks, including the one that killed al-Awlaki.

I completely agree with Wells’ restatement and application of my position on the public authority defence. But I am less sure that Ambinder’s “truth” insulates CIA from potential criminal liability. Ken Dilanian, a leading national-security reporter, had a long article in the Los Angeles Times last month discussing the possibility of the military taking over much of the CIA drone program. Ambinder’s reporting seemed to contradict Dilanian’s article, so I tweeted Dilanian about it. Here was his reply:

Dilanian is right: the articles don’t necessarily contradict each other. Ambinder says that the military flies the drones and pushes the button that launches the weapon; he does not claim that the military chooses the targets and makes the decision to launch the attack. There are some interesting questions about what it means for the CIA to “give the order to fire,” but it seems clear that CIA officers are still involved in lethal drone attacks in a manner that gives rise to a potential violation of the foreign-murder statute — as conspirators or instigators or as aiders-and-abettors. So the fact that a CIA officer is not entitled to a public authority defence remains an important issue.

Print Friendly, PDF & Email
Topics
Foreign Relations Law, International Criminal Law, International Human Rights Law, National Security Law
Notify of
Ian Henderson
Ian Henderson

Customary international law on whether an aircraft is a military aircraft draws a distinction between the ‘crew’ and the person in ‘command’ of the aircraft. This would appear to be a useful way of analysing a situation in which one person is operating the flight controls, the same person or another operating the target acquisition and weapon system, but either or both persons are taking tactical direction from another.

John C. Dehn

As I noted here at OJ after the bin Laden raid, the legal affect of placing the military under the CIA in covert operations is unclear and under-analyzed.  Nevertheless, at the time, almost everyone agreed that the bin Laden operation complied with international humanitarian law.  (Some didn’t agree that IHL applied, and others thought there might be a jus ad bellum problem, but nobody questioned the authority of the SEAL Team to kill bin Laden.)   If the military is working under the CIA’s covert action umbrella, as these articles suggest, then the CIA’s drone program is operating no differently than the bin Laden raid did. When other agencies are placed under the CIA’s control for covert action, they are subject to the rules (or lack thereof) governing the CIA unless otherwise provided.  In a comment to my post, Marty Lederman stated his understanding that the military adhered to its general policy to comply with IHL in such operations.   All of this suggests, as Wells noted, that “unlawful” killing of citizens for purposes of the foreign murder statute does not include the killing of U.S. citizens in the context of armed conflict who are targetable under IHL.  Under such… Read more »

John C. Dehn

Kevin,   My view is that the AUMF provides authority for the President to actuate the war powers of the government.  This authority includes using the CIA in covert operations designed to engage enemy fighters/belligerents/combatants, including those who are citizens, through non-traditional military means.  The net effect of such congressional and presidential authorization is that those agents may lawfully aid in prosecuting the conflict under U.S. domestic law.  This means that they are acting on the public authority of the United States as articulated by Congress and the President.     I don’t think that the White Paper is suggesting that IHL provides authority for the CIA to participate in hostilities.  I think it is saying that American citizens may constitutionally be targeted by the U.S. government under circumstances permitted by IHL. Thus, it is both IHL and the AUMF that makes CIA action lawful for purposes of the foreign murder statute.   This is an entirely separate question from whether agents of the U.S. are entitled to immunity from foreign jurisdictions/prosecutions.  Clearly, some of what the CIA does is entirely consistent with U.S. federal law while violating the domestic criminal law of the state(s) in which they operate.  No… Read more »

John C. Dehn

To state it differently, and to combine my comments, Supreme Court decisions strongly support the proposition that the U.S. government may lawfully use war powers against its citizens when the use of those powers is consistent with the laws of war/international humanitarian law.  Targeting a citizen who is an enemy fighter/combatant/belligerent is consistent with IHL. Therefore, the White Paper relies on IHL, coupled with authority to engage in armed conflict (the AUMF), to establish the lawfulness of a use of lethal force against a enemy citizen fighter/belligerent/combatant.  The case law only addresses the power of the government to invade public and private rights, not the (international) status of the government agent invading those rights.  If the government agent is acting pursuant to domestic authority regardless of international status, it is lawful under domestic law.
 

John C. Dehn

Kevin,
 
The difference between what I am arguing and torture is that separate domestic law — the War Crimes Act — specifically makes it a crime to engage in torture during international or non-international armed conflict.  The act itself is prohibited in the specific context and regardless of the international status of the person engaging in it.  
 
Regarding the killing of an American citizen, Congress has generally prohibited such conduct when “unlawful” without specifically addressing the armed conflict context.  In armed conflict, killing a citizen can be consistent with international and domestic law, and according to the Supreme Court is probably “lawful” when the government’s use of force is lawful under IHL.  
 
Although I’ll go into this in later scholarship, this might mean that the government should be estopped from prosecuting foreign nationals who kill in the context of an armed conflict without meeting IHL requirements for prisoner of war status/combatant immunity (murder in violation of the law of war), at least in some circumstances.

John C. Dehn

No, I am not saying that the AUMF trumps “any” federal statute.  I am saying that it supersedes or provides a relevant exception to clearly inconsistent federal law.  
 
The very text of the AUMF authorizes the President to use military force, interpreted in Hamdi to mean war powers.  Those powers undoubtedly include targeting and detaining enemy fighters/belligerents/combatants.  Supreme Court precedent permits the use of war powers against citizens when they are part of an enemy armed force.  Federal law permits the use of the CIA to engage in a broad range of covert activity, which includes traditional war powers exercised in non-traditional ways.  Thus, the CIA may target and kill enemy fighters/belligerents/combatants who are also citizens.  Doing so is “lawful” for purposes of the foreign murder statute, just as the Court found with regard to detention despite a general federal criminal prohibition.
 
Let me pose this question, Kevin.  If in the course of a covert activity unrelated to an extant armed conflict the CIA encountered an American citizen that posed an immediate threat of grave harm to other citizens, could they engage that threat with lethal force?  Does the “defense of others” justification apply in those circumstances?

John C. Dehn

Reasonable minds may certainly differ, Kevin.  I am offering a plausible view of the legal effect of the AUMF and covert action statutes.  Your view is certainly plausible as well.  If it were an easy question, then nobody in government would have paused to consider it.   My reading is not based on the text or history of the AUMF, however.  It is informed by the history of the CIA and its use in activities related to armed conflict.  You are fundamentally arguing that a general requirement to comply with a relatively context neutral criminal statute (let’s keep in mind that it does not specifically apply to covert action or the CIA by its terms) cannot be the subject of an implied exception.  I am arguing that the law can be reasonably interpreted to grant a context specific implied exception when such an exception is relatively clear and constitutional, as happened in Hamdi.  The exception need not comply with common law understandings of public authority.   Let us hypothetically say that the CIA was used in the initial stages of the invasion of Afghanistan and worked side by side with special forces.  Under the Military Extraterritorial Jurisdiction Act, they would likely be subject to prosecution… Read more »

Jordan
Jordan

There is no “public authority” defense under international law — a la IMT at Nuremberg, just the opposite re: international criminal conduct (which begs the question of course). So the supposed defense is relevant merely to domestic law as such.
In any event, control of drones and targetings by active duty military is more relevant to “combatant” status and “combatant immunity” for lawful acts of war under the laws of war — which should also inform the domestic constitutional issue.  The more interesting question involves implied immunity under the self-defense paradigm when laws of war are not applicable (as noted in my 19 J. Trans. L. & Pol’y article in 2009).  If targeting is permissible under the law of self-defense (in time of peace or in time of war), it appears that general patterns of practice and opinio juris regarding such practices support an implied immunity for lawful self-defense targetings (no known prosecutions, etc.).  This should also inform the domestic constitutional issue.

John C. Dehn

Kevin,   Your view that CIA agents may not claim public authority means that, when operating with U.S. armed forces overseas, they might be prosecuted for killing a foreign fighter under the general federal murder statute (18 U.S.C. sec. 1111) applied through the Military Extraterritorial Jurisdiction Act (MEJA) or the Uniform Code of Military Justice (UCMJ) murder offense.  Either provision might be applied (whether it is constitutional to use the UCMJ we are not yet sure) to civilians serving with or accompanying armed forces overseas in armed conflict or other overseas contingency operations.  (Under their terms, neither MEJA nor UCMJ would apply to independent CIA operations.  Query whether CIA agents “accompany” the armed forces or vice versa in covert action operations.)   When I say that the foreign murder statute does not “specifically” apply to covert action I mean that in the strictest sense of the term.  The statute criminalizes the unlawful killing of one U.S. national by another U.S. national in foreign territory generally.  It would apply to me traveling overseas as an academic.  It only applies to covert action only by a general requirement in the covert action statutes to comply with federal law, not by a specific provision of the… Read more »

Jordan
Jordan

And implied immunity under the international law of self-defense would inform the meaning of “unlawful” killing as “murder” under any relevant domestic law, especially given Charming Betsy and the many other Supreme Court cases that recognize that customary international law, at least, is a necessary background for interpretation of any relevant federal statute — and recall the Cook rule (expressed also in many other Supreme Court cases) that if a federal statute is unavoidably inconsistent with treaty law of the U.S., Congress must clearly and unequivocally express an intent to override the prior treaty law or the treaty law will prevail domestically as law of the United States. All in our IL casebook

John C. Dehn

It’s a good argument, Kevin, but it doesn’t persuade me.  We are not talking about an implicit “repeal” of a statute as that term is commonly used.  At issue is whether the AUMF legitimizes a narrow class of conduct within a criminal statute’s otherwise very broad scope.  Now, I would agree that one shouldn’t readily imply exceptions to criminal statutes. But in this context that implication seems unavoidable.  At any rate, I couldn’t disagree more that the AUMF is broader than the foreign murder statute—quite the contrary.

John C. Dehn

Important update: according to a Lawfare post this morning by Jack Goldsmith, this debate might soon become moot.  Has Kevin’s line of argument persuaded the administration, or at least made them uncomfortable enough to change course?  

Jordan
Jordan

John: and the AUMF’s authorization is necessarily limited by the word appropriate  — but, as recognized in Hamdi, what is appropriate under the laws of war (and presumbably under international law more generally, a la Charming Betsy, etc.) is relevant.

John C. Dehn

I completely agree, Jordan!

John C. Dehn

Some final thoughts:   “Implied repeal” was not the Court’s approach in Hamdi, nor do I think it would be its approach if called upon to address this matter.  Is it really a partial “repeal”—generally meaning “rescission” or “revocation”—for a statute to authorize and make lawful in a specific context that which would be generally unlawful under a broad, generally applicable statute?  Also, generally speaking, when courts are faced with laws that might conflict, they first attempt to harmoniously interpret them, finding a conflict only when those laws are clearly irreconcilable.  It seems to me that doing so in this case would likely yield the result I have suggested, especially in light of the Executive’s (apparent) interpretation.   “Sweeping authorization?”  If it were so sweeping would we now be discussing extra-AUMF threats?  The AUMF has been stretched to the breaking point because it was not sweeping enough to encompass the numerous and varied threats that existed at the time it was enacted and have since then emerged.   It surely depends upon one’s point of view, but I think a statute that categorically bans certain conduct between members of a rather large societal group almost anywhere in the world and regardless of… Read more »