Quick Thoughts on UBL’s Killing — and a Response to Lewis

Quick Thoughts on UBL’s Killing — and a Response to Lewis

A number of students and colleagues have asked me if I believe that Usama bin Laden’s killing was legal. I’m swamped with teaching and writing responsibilities, so my ability to blog is limited.  But I thought I’d at least put my thoughts on record, skeletal though they may be.  And I want to reply to what I think are two misleading statements in Michael Lewis’s post regarding the relationship between the jus ad bellum and the jus in bello.

First, with regard to the UBL question: I have no doubt that killing UBL was legal. To begin with, I think the applicable legal regime is international humanitarian law (IHL), not international human-rights law (IHRL) — a conclusion that can be reached in a number of different ways.  The best rationale is that UBL was a member of an organized armed group (“original” al Qaeda) taking part in the armed conflict in Afghanistan.  In the alternative, I think we can say (although it is a closer call) that the hostilities in Pakistan rise to the level of armed conflict and that UBL was a member of an organized armed group (original al Qaeda or al Qaeda Pakistan, if the two are distinct entities) taking part in that conflict. Either way, UBL was legitimately targetable with lethal force at any time, subject only to the principles of distinction and proportionality.  And nothing I’ve seen indicates that the attack on UBL’s compound violated either of those principles.

Importantly, I don’t think the result would be any different if the applicable regime was IHRL, not IHL.  As I’ve written before, IHRL limits targeted killing more than IHL, but it by no means prohibits it. And I think UBL’s killing was permissible, for reasons articulated by the inestimable Marko Milanovic:

IHRL does allow states to deliberately kill individuals if they have a sufficient justification. OBL was undoubtedly a highly dangerous individual, whose apprehension was needed to protect the lives of others. The US military operation at least contemplated the capture of OBL; the troops on the ground shot him in a firefight. There are no indications that he had tried to surrender before being shot. Under the same facts, his killing would have been equally as lawful had he been hiding somewhere in Alaska rather than in Abbottabad.

Now, to Lewis.  He and I obviously agree that UBL’s kiling was lawful and that the applicable legal regime is IHL, not IHRL.  It is important to recognize, however, that his explanation of why IHL applies rests on an unacceptable conflation of the jus ad bellum and the jus in bello.  He writes:

[S]tate practice strongly supports the view that an expansive reading of Article 51 to include non-state actors is appropriate. Sunday’s operation was another example of state practice undertaken with the belief that the boundaries of the battlefield are not determined by geopolitical lines but rather by the location of participants in an armed conflict, whether the participants are states or non-state actors. This continues to be the standard for determining where the law of armed conflict is properly applied.

The second and third sentences of this statement are correct, but they in no way follow from the first sentence.  IHL applies to the operation for one reason and one reason only: because hostilities rising to the level of armed conflict exist in Afghanistan and/or Pakistan (and UBL was a member of an organized group taking part in one of those conflicts). Whether the operation against UBL is consistent with Article 51 of the UN Charter (which I agree it was) has no bearing on that question; the consistency issue is exclusively one of the jus ad bellum — namely, whether the operation violated Pakistan’s sovereignty. Differently put, if the objective requirements of armed conflict do exist, IHL applies even if Article 51 did not authorize the operation; IHL does not distinguish between just and unjust, legal or illegal, uses of force.  (Which means that it is perfectly legal for a soldier fighting an illegal war to kill an enemy combatant.)  Conversely, if the objective requirements of armed conflict do not exist, IHL does not apply even if Article 51 did authorize the operation.  The jus ad bellum question is irrelevant to the jus in bello one.  (A conclusion reached, it’s worth noting, by the Farben, Krupp, and Ministries tribunals in the aftermath of WW II.)

I would also take issue with this statement in Lewis’s post:

The United States military sent some of its most highly trained combat experts into Pakistan without asking for Pakistan’s permission. They entered Pakistan’s airspace in military helicopters specifically equipped to defeat the Pakistani air defenses. According to a national security official in the immediate aftermath of the operation they went there for the sole purpose of killing Osama bin Laden, a goal which they quickly accomplished. These facts support characterizing this as a military operation conducted under the laws of armed conflict and not a law enforcement operation.

This is not necessarily wrong, but it is at least misleading.  Although how a state chooses to respond to a threat from a non-state actor is relevant to whether hostilities rise to the level of armed conflict, the form of the response — military or law-enforcement — does not determine whether an armed conflict exists.  It is simply one factor, the importance of which is debatable.  States do not get to unilaterally determine whether IHL applies to hostilities with a non-state actor; again, that is an objective question determined by the intensity of the hostilities and the organization of the parties to the conflict.  Nor, it is important to add, would we want states to be able to trigger IHL simply by calling in the military instead of deploying police officers.  If that was the test, the Syrian government would be able to argue that its recent decision to massacre protesters with tanks was governed by IHL, not by IHRL, because the use of tanks means that the massacre was “a military operation conducted under the laws of armed conflict and not a law enforcement operation.”

The bottom line: yes, killing bin Laden was legal.  But it was legal because the operation that killed him complied with IHL, not because it was permitted by Article 51. The latter issue is relevant only to whether Pakistan has the right to complain about the United States’ violation of its sovereignty.

Print Friendly, PDF & Email
Topics
Featured, Foreign Relations Law, International Criminal Law, International Human Rights Law, Middle East, National Security Law, Organizations
Notify of
Dzimi
Dzimi

“There are no indications that he had tried to surrender before being shot,” writes Milanovic.

But there is no evidence of anything; hence these kinds of “arguments” (or mere assertions based on nothing) are quite pointless.

HDW
HDW

Why do you exclude issues of jus ad bellum from the determination of the legality of the US use of force against bin Laden? Surely whether or not the US was entitled to use force in Pakistan is part of the determination of the legality of the operation. Reducing this issue to one of whether Pakistan had a right to “complain” after the fact denies the legal nature of the sovereign right to territorial integrity, and the bindingness of the prohibition of the use of force, which can be circumvented with reliance on Art. 51. There are two sides to the legality of a military strike- jus ad bellum and jus in bello. Why do you deny that violation of the first body of law would not make the strike against bin Laden unlawful?

trackback

[…] Jon Heller, at Opinio Juris, shares his thoughts on the legality of killing bin […]

Mark Kersten

Thanks for the post and sharing your views.

I won’t weigh in on the legality of the killing. However, I want to make a distinction that I think is important and one which is getting lost in the shuffle. There are two general strands of argument in this debate (and others in international law): 1) that the killing of bin Laden is legal and 2) that the killing of bin Laden is just and therefore moral.

Many people will not see the distinction. As international politics is increasingly legalized, justice is increasingly equated with what is legal under international law. I think this may be a good time to remember what Judith Shklar taught us of the dangers of conflating the law with morality.

I think this opens us up to a broader debate which considers not only whether killing bin Laden was legal and therefore just but whether it was legal yet unjust, illegal but just or both illegal and unjust.

Anon
Anon

Please, please, please — at least initially, let the reader know what IHL, not IHRL means.  I want to follow what you are saying, but it’s not like those are such obvious acronyms.  Indeed, there are so obscure to the rest of the world that you can’t find them using google.  Argghh!!!

thanks 🙂

Gerbert
Gerbert

Article 51 is about “armed attacks”, not about people sleeping in bed : “Nothing in the present Charter shall impair the inherent right of individual or collective self-defence if an armed attack occurs against a Member of the United Nations, until the Security Council has taken measures necessary to maintain inter- national peace and security. Measures taken by Members in the exercise of this right of self-defence shall be immediately reported to the Security Council and shall not in any way affect the authority and responsibility of the Security Council under the present Charter to take at any time such action as it deems necessary in order to maintain or restore international peace and security.”

Marty Lederman
Marty Lederman

One thing I’m not sure I quite understand, Kevin.  This sentence:  “Conversely, if the objective requirements of armed conflict do not exist, IHL does not apply even if Article 51 did authorize the operation.” There have, of course, been many examples over the years in which a nation has engaged in isolated acts of self-defense that have not risen to the level of, and have not resulted in, armed conflict.  Indeed, the Caroline doctrine itself, however one might want to characterize it, contemplates such self-defense actions short of armed conflict.  The examples in our own history are legion, including most recently the strikes under Bush I and Clinton in Libya, Sudan, Afghanistan, etc.  (Of course, there is dispute about whether some of these actions were legitimate self-defense; but for present purposes what’s important is that there’s no dispute that there have been many instance such historical cases where the claim of self-defense was justified.) I’ve always assumed that such self-defense actions are governed by IHL, in two important respects.  First, the many constraints of IHL apply — distinction, proportionality, necessity, no perfidy, no denial of quarter, etc.  Second, members of the armed forces of the state or non-state actor against whom the… Read more »

Ian Henderson
Ian Henderson

Dear Prof. Lederman,

For what it is worth, I have an article due for publication around mid-year in the Yearbook of International Humanitarian Law that addresses your exact question. Having expressed the view that certain acts in national self-defence do not rise to the standard of an armed conflict, I conclude that the law of armed conflict cannot apply de jure. So, as a simple example, flattening/expanding bullets would be lawful. I go on to argue that the along with the jus ad bellum concepts of necessity and proportionality, those same legal terms need to be re-thought in the context of not just the resort to use of force but the actual application of that force to a particular target. I then suggest meanings for those terms. I also discuss whether compensation might be payable to bystanders who are injured or have property damaged.

Marty Lederman
Marty Lederman

Very interesting, Ian.  Might I inquire *why* the rules of IHL would not apply?  Would there be any reason for nations not to insist upon the same protections?  Any state practice to the contrary?  For what it’s worth, it is longstanding DOD policy that all of its operations, in armed conflict or not, must comply with IHL — and my understanding is that they fully expect to be entitled to the combatant’s privilege in such cases.

Gerbert
Gerbert

An article which does address the just/unjust issue : http://www.independent.co.uk/opinion/commentators/geoffrey-robertson-why-its-absurd-to-claim-that-justice-has-been-done-2278041.html

If we come to the conclusion that it was legal yet unjust, the next step is to think how the legal context must be reformed so that next time similarly unjust actions can become illegal under the reformed international law.

Marty Lederman
Marty Lederman

Kevin:  Thanks very much; that certainly tees up the issue cleanly!  Suffice it to say that your views about (i) the non-application of IHL to acts of self-defense short of armed conflict, and (ii) especially, the absence of any combatant privilege in a NIAC; are deeply contrary to U.S. understandings.

Is there persuasive authority for either proposition?

Ian Henderson
Ian Henderson

Prof Lederman, As a colleague of mine regularly accuses me of being, I took a black-letter, positivist approach to the issue. How could the laws of armed conflict (the law of war) legally apply to a situation that is not an armed conflict? As LOAC grants rights as well as imposes limitations, I think it is very important to realise that LOAC applies de jure only to an armed conflict. I have often discussed the DoD policy you mention with my US colleagues. As you point out, it is policy. It seems, ipso facto, that the US is of the view that the LOAC does not apply legally to those situations. I’ll claim that as State practice to show that LOAC does not apply de jure outside an armed conflict 🙂 Importantly, the US can accept restrictions (eg, no flattening bullets, no perfidy) as a matter of policy, but cannot grant itself rights (eg, detention as a ‘PW’, shoot-to-kill based on ‘combatant status’) as a matter of policy. As Prof. Heller has brought it up, please note I also discuss in my article the issue of an equivalent to a combatant’s privilege for government forces in both a NIAC (I argue… Read more »

Marty Lederman
Marty Lederman

Kevin:  I do not mean to question your expertise — you know much more about these questions than I — but it would be very helpful to me if you could point to where the “ICRC also clearly rejects both positions” and to any authority that these “are foundational principles of IHL and always have been.”

As I said in response to Ian, I can’t think of any obvious reason why nation states would not want such rules to apply to such self-defense and NIAC situations — of course, with any articulated adjustments that might be demanded by the distinct nature of such military actions — or why they would not customarily act in accordance with them, as the US military traditionally has done.  You raise the issue of civil wars.  But of course Lincoln/Lieber insisted, quite famously, that the laws of war do apply to such a conflict.

Marty Lederman
Marty Lederman

Kevin:  Article 1(2) does not “explicitly limit the application of IHL to hostilities that involve a certain level of intensity and continue for a certain length of time” and to NIACs covered by APII, nor does it preclude the application of IHL to acts of self-defense not rising to the level of armed conflict.  Instead, it merely provides that the treaty requirements of APII itself are so limited in scope:  “This Protocol . . . shall apply . . . .”  Customary IHL is left unaffected — and my assumption is that such customary law applies both to acts of self-defense and to NIACs.

Marty Lederman
Marty Lederman

To step back for a minute and put this discussion in broader focus:  As I’ve argued to Kevin in the past, I am frankly surprised that human rights supporters are so reluctant to acknowledge that IHL applies in these cases — namely, to acts of self-defense short of armed conflict, and to NIACs.  The application of IHL in such cases is overwhelmingly a positive thing, bringing with it as it does substantial humanitarian protections for civilians and soldiers alike.  That’s why some in the Bush Administration were so eager to deny its application (and the application of Common Article 3), and why it was such a momentous and salutary development when the Court held in Hamdan that CA3 does apply.  If international law were to settle on the view that IHL does not apply in such contexts, I have little doubt that nation states would feel far less constrained, and act in a much less constrained and humanitarian manner, in their use of force in such contexts. Of course, the flip side, of sorts, is that although customary IHL imposes numerous very important constraints on the use of force, it also establishes combatant immunity for uses of force by state… Read more »

Marty Lederman
Marty Lederman

Kevin:  With particular respect to your comment about duration and intensity, I did not write, nor suggest, that IHL applies to any and all uses of military force.  All I suggested was that where such use of force satisfies jus ad bellum requirements — in particular, where there is (i) a NIAC (in which case there is the requisite intensity and duration, even in cases where APII does not apply), or (ii) where a nation acts in legitimate self-defense (where there might not be such intensity and duration), the nation must comply with the jus in bello of IHL — and where its armed forces do so, they are entitled to the combatant’s privilege.

I am unaware of any authorities establishing that the use of force in such cases need not comply with the jus in bello, or that armed forces who so comply can still be guilty of murder.  Not saying there’s no such authority out there — only that I’m not aware of it.

Gerbert
Gerbert

A test for any argument based on the non-state status of the targeted person should be what happens when that non-state person happens to be hiding inside the borders of the United States and the killing action takes place within the borders of the United States. Does the principle of separation of powers remain unscathed ?

Marty Lederman
Marty Lederman

Kevin:  Alas, I think we’re now in an infinite loop.  No, we don’t agree that the combatant’s privilege cannot exist outside of IHL, let alone not outside IACs.

And no, I did not deny that IHL might even apply in situations where the use of force was unjustified, such as in the FarbenKrupp, and Ministries cases.  My point is simply that state armed forces are not immune from the requirements of IHL (or denied its protections) where, at a minimum, the use of force is lawful in cases of self-defense and NIAC.  Is there any authority indicating that in such cases, armed forces are not bound by, e.g., the IHL requirements of humanity and necessity and distinction, or that they need not comply with the prohibitions on perfidy, denial of quarter, outlawry, etc.?  Or that they can be prosecuted for murder, consistent with international law, where they have complied with such IHL norms?

Marty Lederman
Marty Lederman

forgot to add:  And perhaps just as importantly, as I discuss a couple of comments ago, even if the law were uncertain on this question (and I’m still not convinced), why would it be in the interest of human rights proponents such as ourselves to insist that IHL does not apply in such cases?  I fear that nothing good would come of such a view if it were to prevail.

John C. Dehn

Kevin and Marty, If I may, the reason that the treaties cited by Kevin are limited in their application is that states originally wanted it that way.  If you check the negotiating histories, states DID NOT want to be bound by IHL unless they were assured of some willingness and ability for non-state actor compliance.   Thus, STATES created the protracted hostilities of sufficient intensity and “sufficient organization” requirements.  What states did not intend, I think (and in spite of the case law of international tribunals), is filling of the legal lacunae in this framework — meaning for a response to armed attacks by non-state actors not amounting to armed conflict — to be governed by human rights law, particularly extraterritorially.  In such cases, states may observe IHL as a matter of policy or by analogy but had no requirement to do so as a matter of law.  This, I think, is Jordan Paust’s position, and somewhat reflects the U.S. position (depending, perhaps, upon the administration). While I respect Kevin immensely, he frequently argues, without citation, that no European country views the law this way.  Absent a thorough study, I can’t bring myself to fully agree.  I agree that a great many European… Read more »

John C. Dehn

And please forgive my many typos…

Michael W. Lewis

Kevin, Marty and John, I hope my comment is not arriving too late for your reactions.  Kevin cites APII and the Rome Statute with large numbers of signatories (over 160 and 110 respectively) as evidence that these treaties can be recognized as customary international law.  However customary law must be supported by state practice as well as treaty signatures.  I am unaware of any situation in which states that have actually been involved in conflicts with non-state actors have eschewed the right of self-defense against such parties, even when they had to cross international borders to exercise that right.  Colombia (a party to both APII and Rome) crossed the border into Ecuador to strike FARC camps there.  Turkey crossed into Iraq to strike the PKK.  Israel crossed into Lebanon to strike Hezbollah.  Back in the 1970’s the US crossed into Cambodia and Laos to strike the Viet Cong.  More recently the US has entered Afghanistan to go after al Qaeda (with UN support) and has entered Pakistan without Pakistani permission in pursuit of al Qaeda as well.   Plenty of states may have signed APII and the Rome Statute, but I am not aware of any nation that has actually been involved in an… Read more »

Michael W. Lewis

Sorry.  To finish I just ask for any counter examples in which states involved in armed conflicts with non-state actors have recognized international boundaries as legally foreclosing their ability to strike the non-state actors in self-defense.  I am not aware of any, but they certainly may exist.

Michael Drew
Michael Drew

I’m not following what this all really hinges on.  Imagine the unlikely scenario in which the U.S. elects to employ a drone a attack as the means to kill bin Laden, and successfully does so while injuring no one else.  Is your analysis different?  Is there a number of civilians or others killed who are not party to armed conflict that you would say would make this operation illegal?  Is it a matter of degree of certainty that the U.S. must have that no more than x number of noncombatants are likely to be killed in a given strike?  Or would simply any operation intended to kill bin Laden been legal?  Presumably that’s impossible to say, because at some point some level of destruction of human life will be out of proportion to whatever is being retaliated for.  But exactly against what is propostionality measured.  Is it measured on a by0target basis, i.e. bin Laden was responsible for at least 3000 American deaths, so up to 3000 incidental deaths to his killing would be proportionate?  How are any of these thresholds and comparisons – i.e. the triggering of IHL and proportionality – actually measured?

Michael Drew
Michael Drew

Also what comments would Kevin have about this article: http://afpak.foreignpolicy.com/posts/2011/05/04/the_bin_laden_aftermath_abbottabad_and_international_law, where an author whom I think is known here argues, among a lot of other things, that, “On May 2, no fighting was going on in Pakistan that would rise to the level of “armed conflict” as defined under international law[…]”?

Gerbert
Gerbert

If International law makes the Abbottabad raid legal, doesn’t it make the French operation in Auckland (New Zealand) in 1985 (sinking of the Rainbow Warrior) simultaneously legal ?

Ian Henderson
Ian Henderson

Dear Gerbert,

I do not believe so. I doubt that it would be a good argument to suggest that France was involved in a NIAC with Greenpeace. Nor does it seem arguable that the Rainbow Warrior was involved in (even in the anticipatory sense) an armed attack on France or its national interests.

Michael W. Lewis

Kevin,

Thanks for the response.  Let me try to reiterate your position and tell me if I am getting it right.  Article 51 self-defense against non-state actors requires the existence of an armed conflict, as opposed to self-defense against state actors which merely requires an armed attack.  In the bin Laden example you find that there is an armed conflict between al Qaeda (original) and the US that bin Laden is participating in, therefore the self-defense jus ad bellum justification for the killing is valid.  Is that correct?  If so, would the killing have been equally valid if bin Laden had been in Yemen?

To clarify one point from my post that you were commenting upon.  My reference to the SEALs and the manner in which the operation took place was merely done to clarify the fact that the US was treating this as a military operation not a law enforcement operation.  I agree with you that the mere fact that the US characterizes it that way does not make it so legally (your Syrian tank example).  My purpose in mentioning that was to answer MEO’s claim that the US undertook this as a law enforcement operation.

Thanks for your responses. 

trackback

[…] OpinoJuris: Kevin Jon Heller: Quick Thoughts on UBL’s Killing – and a Response to Lewis […]

trackback

[…] Jon Heller, at Opinio Juris, shares his thoughts on the legality of killing bin Laden. Heller maintains that: “I have no doubt that killing […]

trackback

[…] Jon Heller, Quick Thoughts on UBL’s Killing, and a Response to Lewis (Opinio Juris, May 4, 2011)(legal under international humanitarian law […]

Rob
Rob

Hi Kevin,
Thanks for sharing your views. Just for my understanding of the legality of OBL’s killing: Leaving ius ad bellum aside and focussing on ius in bello, if we assume that there is a NIAC between the US and AL Qaeda (involving OBL) – I can live with that reasoning – doesnt the legality of the killing then depend on the specific circumstances of the killing? I mean all it says is that OBL is a legitimate target, so could be killed unless he laid down arms, was detained or clearly surrendered, no? The current info from US we have is that he was unarmed but that there were weapons within his reach – if that is true, I could leave with the reasoning that as a legitimate target he could be killed legally. If he clearly surrendered though (being out of reach of weapons) I think it would have been illegal. What do you think?

Thanks for your reactions

Rob

trackback

[…] of the killing of Osama bin Laden has led to  a variety of opinion on the webspace. See here, here, here (Foreign Policy), and here. Categories: Public International Law Tags: “Unwilling […]

W.C.L
W.C.L

Dear Professor Kevin Jon Heller,

According to you first post : ”
“The bottom line: yes, killing bin Laden was legal.  But it was legal because the operation that killed him complied with IHL, not because it was permitted by Article 51. The latter issue is relevant only to whether Pakistan has the right to complain about the United States’ violation of its sovereignty.”

as you argued,IHl doesnot apply to NIAC and situations not amounted to armed conflict, how can American troops have combatant privilege to kill Laden?

Or there are other reasons to have such killings legal?

Thank you.

Leonard
Leonard

I disagree with both Lewis’ and Heller’s analysis. Heller: If one argues that OBL ‘s killing falls under IHL, one can not do that without establishing that a CURRENT armed conflict between both the US and Al-Qaida existed at the time of the use of force against OBL. Its my understanding that the US are not currently engaged in an armed conflict on Pakistani territory. And in Afghanistan enemy combatants are at time  (afghan) Taliban not Al-Qaida. The “war on terror” is in general sense a political doctrine, which by itself doesn’t establish circumstances falling under the term “armed conflict” necessary for IHL application. Lewis: The idea that this a case of Art. 51 UN Charta is a strange one. Leaving aside that by prevailing opinion it does not apply to non-state actors: Use of force under Art. 51 demands a current or at least imminent threat and the force applied has to be necessary and appropriate to end the attack. In the words of Webster/Caroline: “(The threat has to be) instant, overwhelming, and leaving no choice of means, and no moment for deliberation”. I doubt that the general characterization of OBL being a potential dangerous person (if he still was at all) would fall… Read more »