Osiel on “Rethinking the Law of War Crimes”

Osiel on “Rethinking the Law of War Crimes”

The following is a guest-post — actually a short book-proposal — by my friend Mark Osiel, the Aliber Family Chair in Law at the University of Iowa.  I have agreed to post it despite the inordinate jealousy I feel toward his remarkable productivity.  Mark would greatly appreciate comments and criticisms, especially examples and counter-examples of what he is trying to get at.

Rethinking the Law of War Crimes: “Collateral Damage”and “Distinction”

Current law on war crimes is deeply disappointing to most people – public and legal professional — who pay it any attention, notwithstanding many prosecutions for mass atrocity by new international courts in recent years. Observers on both the Right and Left agree that the law’s expectations in this area depart radically from those of morality, that is, from any defensible conception of what a truly “just war” would look like, how it would be fought. Most concur that the relevant rules are far too generous to fighters at some points, too demanding of them at others; too weak in protecting innocent civilians, too indulgent of violence by other civilians. Wide agreement also exists that obvious aggressors would, in a genuinely just law of war, enjoy less legal protection than their aggrieved victims. The law will have nothing of this.

Those on the Left, especially, insist that a just law of war crimes would preclude the cynical invocation of “collateral damage” to excuse the eminently foreseeable killing of many innocents that has occurred in several recent confrontations. Many on the Right, particularly, proceed to denounce the habitual exploitation of civilian status and its protections by those organizing large-scale terror attacks on population centers while deploying their own civilians to “shield” military installations from counter-attack. Both ends of the political spectrum, as well as many people in between, concur that the disjuncture between law and justice has grown so great that longstanding international rules of war no longer merit respect or adherence. It is no exaggeration to describe the current situation as something of a crisis, one that – given its moral magnitude — should concern any conscientious citizen of the world.

How did the respective demands of law and morality in war apparently come to deviate so profoundly? Might anything be done to realign them?

The conventional account of law’s failings accusingly points to the world’s military powers who, immersed in the anarchy of global politics, find it necessary to make hard-hearted calculations of national self-interest in ways that severely limit the moral ambit and aspirations of international law. Some find this situation acceptable; most consider it deplorable. They nonetheless agree on the causal story and its implications for likely legal progress.

There is a different type of obstacle, however, no less weighty if rarely noticed. Attending to it may even help us reassess the apparent constraints of realpolitik itself, by identifying weaknesses in the law better attributable to other factors. The central problem is that, despite millennia of human experience with war and significant advances in its genuinely scientific aspects, those who professionally make (and study) it have few clear answers to several of its perennial puzzles and little ability accurately to predict its ever-shifting contours. In light of these cognitive shortfalls, as we may call them, it should come as little surprise that we have learned so little about how best to govern war, and in particular, about where exactly to draw the line – amidst the ubiquitous violence that is intrinsic to war — between its lawful and criminal features. We must rethink important features of war crimes law from this more skeptical, Socratic vantage point.

The most insistent questions therefore become, at the level of particular legal doctrines: What does the law of war crimes assume about how much of what kind of information, technical and ethical, fighters at all levels know or can be expected to acquire? When, and on what empirical basis, are these assumptions warranted? Finally, can law’s frequent departures from the apparent requirements of justice – as seen through the abstract lens of ideal-theory — be better ascribed to cognitive shortfalls than to constraints of realpolitik? These questions lead us to pose a host of still more specific queries, virtually never raised by legal scholars of war crime.

Consider quickly a few of these. The law requires commanders to employ no more force than “necessary” to achieve a given military aim. But how much do they really know about the measure of force required to achieve a given tactical goal before undertaking it? Might the limits of their understanding here explain the relative lenience of courts when judging them?

The law further demands that “incidental” harm to civilian life and property not become excessive “in relation to the concrete and direct overall military advantage anticipated.” On what kinds of learning do soldiers rely when weighing the competing values in balance here? To say that these values – innocent life versus military success — are incommensurable (as philosophers often do) is simply a more technical way of saying that we know of no acceptable means for measuring them along a single scale?

For that matter, when commanders try to anticipate likely military advantage from a tactical exercise of force, what must they know about how their contemplated action contributes to larger operational and strategic goals? If the law expects very much here, it almost immediately exceeds the limits of what soldiers know. If it demands very little, requiring awareness only of immediate effects, then it ignores how an exercise of force “disproportionate” at the tactical level can sometimes greatly advance the prospects of operational and even strategic victory. This is illustrated as in the sinking of the Belgrano by Britain during the Falklands/Malvinas War. The ship posed no tactical threat at the time and place, but its destruction contributed greatly to Argentina’s decision to abandon the Islands.

Conversely, a tactically “proportionate” use of force sometimes turns out to have highly prejudicial consequences for strategic goals, as when vivid images of a small number of innocent civilian deaths from a successful drone strike on a major terrorist are broadcast across the globe on Al Jazeera. If international legitimacy for nation-building efforts is the central strategic aim, then legal assessments of proportionality in the use of force become inseparable from the public’s moral assessment of whether excessive harm has been caused, however unintentionally, as Dale Stephens observes. Because public opinion blows ephemerally in the wind, no workable legal test of proportionality – and surely none of international criminal law – could be built on this basis. In sum, what is proportionate at one level of military decision-making is often disproportional at another, in ways that elude the law’s convincing conceptual grasp. This contributes to the danger of criminalizing what are simply reasonable disagreements – professional and more political — over the necessary measure of force in a given circumstance.

Once thinking in this epistemic sort of way, we find other such puzzles immediately suggesting themselves. “Effects-based” targeting has become popular among U.S. Air Force strategists, though it entails intentional targeting of civilians, i.e., civilian leaders – in both government and business – upon whose support the criminal policies of a repressive state, such as Serbia’s toward Kosovo in 1999, critically depend. From a moral point of view, effecting policy change in this way would clearly be preferable to targeting thousands of reluctant Serbian conscripts. The advocates of effects-based targeting are right in thinking that we often have information permitting more fine-grained distinctions of threat and culpability for aggression and war crime than those entailed in a bright-line distinction of status between combatant and civilian.

But actual experience with effects-based targeting is discouraging about our capacity to predict the true consequences, intended and unintended, of such civilian targeting. If our powers of social analysis were more advanced, if they strongly suggested which civilian elites to target in order to produce what changes of criminal policy, we would all surely support the legal revisions necessary to permit this. Despite the bluster of its defenders, however, we simply lack the learning to render this theory workable.

Another illustration: When the strategic decision-makers of Western powers contemplate assassinating a leading terrorist, to what extent do they think, know, and worry about how this may implicitly advance such a practice as an incipient customary right and thereby expose their own successors and allies to greater risk of similar attack in turn? If they were certain of their de facto power to prevent such rejoinder, they would have little hesitation about advancing such a de jure norm, in the knowledge it would not come back to haunt them in practice. They do not do so. How much does their inescapable ignorance of such long-range repercussions restrain them from officially acknowledging the fact of these attacks and defending their legality (as some at Opinio Juris urge they should), attacks greatly increased under the Obama administration?

Finally, many non-lawyers today demand that jus in bello restrictions on acceptable means of fighting no longer remain entirely indifferent to jus ad bellum rules on resort to force. Such people – both ordinary citizens and moral thinkers – increasingly believe that a lesser measure of incidental civilian loss is appropriate when grave doubts arise about the underlying cause such force claims to advance. In other words, when evaluating a particular lethal action in war, most people refuse to isolate this question from their broader assessment of the actor’s initial resort to, and continuing employment of force in the first instance. They simply repudiate the law’s historic insistence on such a separation — and hence too reject the idea that proportionality must have distinct meaning in these disparate contexts, as the law continues to insist.

Yet to what extent can soldiers beneath the highest echelons can be expected to recognize whether the war aims for which they fight are just, or consistent with the United Nations Charter? What does the evidence suggest about their propensity to reach conclusions on such matters independently of their superiors’ explanations and exhortations? When reasonable people throughout the world disagree profoundly over the justice of given war aims, it is a perilous for international law to enshrine some contested answer to the question, making it the basis of criminal liability.

There is some recognition of this problem in how the U.N. Charter severely curtails the broader, theological rationales for just resort to force, focusing almost exclusively on national self-defense against armed attack, with the latter term defined quite narrowly. There is further such recognition in the recent efforts to define the crime of “aggression” so that only top policymakers may be held liable for it. They are in the best position to know both the pertinent strategic facts and their own, true rationales for a policy of war.

My working hypothesis is that such inquiries will suggest that the central obstacle to a better law of war crimes lies less in the tough imperatives of geopolitics, as “realists” are wont to insist, than in these cognitive considerations, more subtle and conceptually elusive. For lack of a better word (and at some risk of portentousness), we might call these considerations “epistemic.” To suggest that this is where we should direct our inquiries, however, is not to imply that such challenges necessarily prove any more tractable than the better-known and more brutal ones of realpolitik.

The upshot of such an analysis will be to refute criticism of war crimes law from the Right, to the effect that such is too demanding (with respect to distinction) and critique from the Left (with regard to proportionality) that it is not demanding enough. In other words, the law of war crimes can do more good work than the Right generally allows, but less than the Left invariably demands. The legal status quo in this area, however disappointing from the perspective of any ideal theory of justice, is pretty much the best we can expect for a long time.

All suggestions welcome on how to develop (and qualify) this argument!

Print Friendly, PDF & Email
Topics
Foreign Relations Law, International Criminal Law, International Human Rights Law, Organizations
Notify of
G. M. Beresford Hartwell

May I suggest that use of of “left” and “right” in this context is absurd and capable of being meretricious?  I do not presume to judge wheter or not it is intentional.  The facts are, however, that the atrocities of war and the excesses of security forces are committed in equal number and with equal ferocity by both: Hitler and Stalin; the Stasi and the CIA.  The tragedy is that the intellegensia still seek to find excuses for their own while pretending to condemn the other. “Left” and “right” are the same: enemies of the centre.

Jordan
Jordan

Response…
I hope that the author will pay some attention to the details of the laws of war at some point — because human shileds do not shield persons, proportionality is part of the law of war re: target selection and targetings, civilians who take an aciive and direct part in hostilities are targetable, and so forth. 
Jordan J. Paust

Patrick S. O'Donnell

I’ve found (no surprise here) Larry May’s book, War Crimes and Just War (2007) helpful for thinking through at least some of the questions you raise here, indeed, I think it goes some distance in sketching a “middle way” of the sort you seek (as described in the last para.). However, apparently you’re thinking of something a bit different than what Larry has proposed so I’m curious as to what you think of his book

Peter Orlowicz
Peter Orlowicz

I’m a bit confused at the use of the sinking of the Belgrano as an illustration of the proportionality principle at the tactical level. The Belgrano was a naval warship, not a civilian target or noncombatant; the law of war has never forbidden the attack or destruction of an active military asset in that manner that I’m aware of. Extending the principle in this manner would seem to suggest destruction of a submarine in harbor or drydock in a military base would be disproportionate because the targeted vessel “posed no tactical threat at the time and place”, and that seems disingenuous at best.

The only real example of proportionality I can think of with regard to legitimate military targets, and not civilian casualties or protected persons like POWs involves the use of certain weapons for prohibited purposes. Use of weapons such as white phosphorous for the explicit and sole purpose of increasing enemy suffering is not a legitimate use of military force, for instance, but the issue there is the method used, not the target it’s employed against.

Patrick S. O'Donnell

Cf. Larry May on “proportionality:” “The proportionality principle is on one level the easiest to understand, but on another level it is the most difficult. On the first level, the principle of proportionality simply says that the amount of force of a tactic of war must be neither too strong nor too weak for the task to be accomplished. On the second level, the problem is to identify the relevant ways in which tactics and tasks are to be related and how tasks themselves are to be individuated. The second level is enormously difficult. [….] Proportionality does not merely say that tactics must not cause more suffering than they prevent. Proportionality is only an attenuated utilitarian principle, for there is a core concern that sets a fairly rigid moral limit. There must be no morally less costly way to accomplish a military objective that is thought to be necessary. If there is such a less costly means available, then the principle of proportionality forbids the use of the more costly tactic, regardless of how important the objective is–that is, no matter that we are in a situation of extreme emergency. [….] Of course, if a tactic is literally necessary to… Read more »

Peter Orlowicz
Peter Orlowicz

I would still quibble with the use of the Belgrano as an example of a disproportionate tactical action, I think. I’m also not sure I find Mr. May’s analysis convincing in terms of defining war crimes; I can’t imagine any rational debate reaching the conclusion that sinking a enemy naval warship during a time of war was a war crime due to concerns of disproportionality.

Perhaps it depends on how broadly we define “military objective”. Neutralizing an enemy asset of war (here, a naval warship) can certainly be a legitimate military objective. Is that the objective we’re testing for proportionality? Or do we have to view the sinking of the vessel only in relation to its current tactical threat level to another operation? If so, then it seems likely you can make the same argument for the sinking of the Bismarck during World War II once its rudder was hit and the ship lost steering. Again, I don’t see that as anything even approaching a war crime.

Patrick S. O'Donnell

Peter, I did not claim that May thought the sinking of the ship was a war crime: how did you come up with that? The quote was meant to illustrate the difficulty associated with determining what the proportionality principle permits and disallows, and the decision to sink the ship could plausibly be said to illustrate these difficulties. And for May, this principle is closely related to the principle of necessity and thus one must appreciate if not understand the proper relation between these two principles. Furthermore, both of these principles are interpreted in light of the more fundamental principle of humane treatment. Now May does happen to think that this principle is more stringent than the manner in which it is usually interpreted, but neither May nor I claimed or implied that the sinking of the ship was necessarily a war crime. If alternative tactics were available to accomplish the same result with noticeably less suffering and death then, yes, the sinking would seem to be a disproportionate action. In other words, the military objective must be closely tied to the particular tactic employed or, put differently, “it should be clear that more good than bad is done by the use of a… Read more »