Youngstown and Negative Pragmatism

Youngstown and Negative Pragmatism

I had the good fortune to visit Columbia Law School last week to debate with Sarah Cleveland the merits and demerits of constitutional comparativism. It was a first class program with an introduction from ASIL President Jose Alvarez and thoughtful reflections from the panelists.

The low point for me was the attempt by one speaker (not Alvarez, Cleveland or Jackson) to caricature the detractors of constitutional comparativism by highlighting their worst excesses. One can almost always identify fringe voices on the right (or left) to suggest that the other side is not serious. While it is true that extreme elements on the right have engaged in extraordinarily lamentable behavior in response to Lawrence and Roper (i.e., calls for Kennedy’s impeachment, bizarre chat room death threats, etc.), it does not advance the conversation to highlight those elements and ignore the respectable opposing voices. As I have discussed in a recent symposium piece in the Albany Law Review, eminent scholars such as Richard Posner, Charles Fried, Ernest Young, Daniel Halberstam, Mary Ann Glendon, Jed Rubenfeld, Michael Ramsey and Ken Anderson have thoughtfully expressed numerous reasons for disquiet about the trend toward constitutional comparativism. It is far more fruitful to rebut their positions than belittle a caricature of the opposing side. Conversely, I may not agree with everything that Harold Koh, Mark Tushnet, Gerald Neuman, Vicki Jackson, Sarah Cleveland, Michel Rosenfeld, Melissa Waters, or Jeremy Waldron say about the virtues of constitutional comparativism, but I have the utmost respect for their scholarship and take their positions seriously.

The high point for me (in addition to debating Cleveland) was the presentation by Vicki Jackson on the historical use of constitutional comparativism. Both Cleveland and Jackson have done extensive and thoughtful work in this area, and Jackson had some interesting reflections on the historical use of foreign and international material. I especially liked her references to Youngstown, a case that is often ignored in this discussion. She emphasized that there are some interesting paragraphs in Justice Jackson’s Youngstown concurrence that address comparative experiences with executive emergency powers. Here is the relevant section from Justice Jackson’s concurrence:

Aside from suspension of the privilege of the writ of habeas corpus in time of rebellion or invasion, when the public safety may require it, they made no express provision for exercise of extraordinary authority because of a crisis. I do not think we rightfully may so amend their work, and, if we could, I am not convinced it would be wise to do so, although many modern nations have forthrightly recognized that war and economic crises may upset the normal balance between liberty and authority. Their experience with emergency powers may not be irrelevant to the argument here that we should say that the Executive, of his own volition, can invest himself with undefined emergency powers.

Germany, after the First World War, framed the Weimar Constitution, designed to secure her liberties in the Western tradition. However, the President of the Republic, without concurrence of the Reichstag, was empowered temporarily to suspend any or all individual rights if public safety and order were seriously disturbed or endangered. This proved a temptation to every government, whatever its shade of opinion, and in 13 years suspension of rights was invoked on more than 250 occasions. Finally, Hitler persuaded President Von Hindenberg to suspend all such rights, and they were never restored.

The French Republic provided for a very different kind of emergency government known as the “state of siege.” It differed from the German emergency dictatorship, particularly in that emergency powers could not be assumed at will by the Executive but could only be granted as a parliamentary measure. And it did not, as in Germany, result in a suspension or abrogation of law but was a legal institution governed by special legal rules and terminable by parliamentary authority.

Great Britain also has fought both World Wars under a sort of temporary dictatorship created by legislation. As Parliament is not bound by written constitutional limitations, it established a crisis government simply by delegation to its Ministers of a larger measure than usual of its own unlimited power, which is exercised under its supervision by Ministers whom it may dismiss. This has been called the “high-water mark in the voluntary surrender of liberty,” but, as Churchill put it, “Parliament stands custodian of these surrendered liberties, and its most sacred duty will be to restore them in their fullness when victory has crowned our exertions and our perseverance.” Thus, parliamentary control made emergency powers compatible with freedom.

This contemporary foreign experience may be inconclusive as to the wisdom of lodging emergency powers somewhere in a modern government. But it suggests that emergency powers are consistent with free government only when their control is lodged elsewhere than in the Executive who exercises them. That is the safeguard that would be nullified by our adoption of the “inherent powers” formula. Nothing in my experience convinces me that such risks are warranted by any real necessity, although such powers would, of course, be an executive convenience.


Vicki Jackson added that those paragraphs from Youngstown are almost never included in constitutional law casebooks, such that a whole generation of students remains ignorant of a prominent example of constitutional comparativism.

She is right. As I have previously written in this article, “[p]ragmatism is the leading candidate for a constitutional theory that can credibly justify recourse to comparative material.” (Of course, it goes without saying that Roper and Lawrence are not examples of pragmatism). As I discussed, the Supreme Court has occasionally relied on “negative pragmatism” to highlight foreign experiences that should not be followed:

There are, of course, a handful of cases in which the Court has used comparative empiricism negatively to warn against extreme responses of totalitarian regimes to curtail civil liberties. These cases offer a parade of horribles of state infringements on basic civil liberties. For example, in Shaughnessy v. United States the Court stated: “No society is free where government makes one person’s liberty depend upon the arbitrary will of another. Dictatorships have done this since time immemorial. They do now [in Russia, China and Nazi Germany] . . . . Our Bill of Rights was written to prevent such oppressive practices.” Such negative pragmatism highlights competing systems of government that offer extreme representations of oppressive violations of civil liberties. Uncivilized systems are presented for derision, not emulation. This is hardly the sort of pragmatism to which Justice Breyer aspires.

A lesser variant of negative pragmatism is found when the Court examines comparative experiences only for the purpose of rejecting the foreign approach as inappropriate. In Raines v. Byrd, the Court noted that “[t]here would be nothing irrational about a system that granted standing [to legislatures, as] . . . some European constitutional courts operate under one or another variant of such a regime. . . . But it is obviously not the regime that has obtained under our Constitution.” In Washington v. Glucksberg the Court noted evidence in the Netherlands supports the legislative concern that opening the door to physician-assisted suicide could affect a broader license to practice euthanasia that would be difficult to police and contain. “Euthanasia in the Netherlands has not been limited to competent, terminally ill adults who are enduring physical suffering, and . . . regulation of the practice may not have prevented abuses in cases involving vulnerable persons.” The Court thus utilized the Dutch experience as evidence of the potential evils that might result from regulation as compared with prohibition, intimating that the problems in the Dutch experiment supported the state’s argument for a rational basis in banning the practice. But positive experiences from abroad are less frequently invoked to support pragmatic empiricism.

Thus, negative pragmatism has occasionally been used to highlight aberrant foreign practices or advance American distinctions. With negative pragmatism, foreign experiences are offered as object lessons of what not to do.

Print Friendly, PDF & Email
Topics
General
Notify of
jvarisco

Is it fair to compare Youngstown, which involves foreign policy, and domestic decisions? It is one thing to use some history to support a relatively straightforward decision (Congress in this case clearly opposed the president, and in fact gave him a way of resolving the strike he chose not to use). It is quite another to use it to create a constitutional right because of foreign attitudes/practices. Youngstown was also not about the government exceeding the Constitution (the federal government clearly had the authority to seize the steel mills if it chose) but of legislative versus executive powers. So I’m not really sure if that passage has much relevance to the opinion regardless – individual liberties (e.g. of the steel mills) were not the question.

I suppose one could use any historical passages in foreign policy decisions to support comparativism, but this seems a bit dubious to me.